A bit of prehistory background

It was in 1857, in the Neander Valley cave, in Germany, that an archaeologist first stumbled upon the remains of an ancient, never-before-encountered type of human skull. The skull he discovered was larger in size than that of the Modern Man’s, indicating primarily a larger brain, although likely one not quite as efficient (1).

1. The Sociocultural Hypothesis

The Sociocultural Hypotheses for the evolution of human language suggests that the capacity for humans to communicate via spoken language arises as a result of empiricism and social learning. It proposes that language is an external phenomenon, and in no way, shape, or form, a genetic one (3).

“The presumption was that our minds at birth were blank slates on to which the rules and quirks of our native languages were written.”

— Bill Bryson, Mother Tongue

This theory of the evolution of human language largely follows a framework originally put forth by a psychologist named Vygotsky.

  • there are no features universal to all languages
  • there is no innate genetic knowledge of language
  • and that there exists no domain-specific mechanism for the ability to communicate

Criticisms for the SCT

There are issues with this theory, however, and critics are quick to point out that because cultural evolution does not take place in a biological vacuum, it then becomes impossible to separate the language phenomenon from its physiological constraints (6).

2. The Nativist Perspective

In stark contrast to the SCT, the Nativist Perspective maintains that, in order for humans to have developed the capacity for language, some innate, biological endowment of this ability must have occurred.

“People know how to talk in more or less the same sense that spiders know how to spin webs.”

— Steven Pinker, The Language Instinct

Noam Chomsky, a linguist and renowned historian, famously argued, not only that certain structural facets of speech must be genetic, but also that all languages must share particular universal characteristics that are acquired via domain-specific mechanisms within the brain (8).

2.1 The By-Product Hypothesis

The By-Product Hypothesis differs dramatically from the Sociocultural Hypothesis, in that it implicates the human capacity for language as a by-product or co-occurrence of the process of natural selection.

  • there is some form of innate genetic knowledge of language
  • there exists a domain-specific mechanism for the ability to communicate
  • that language is exaptive (meaning a by-product of a naturally selected mechanism), not adaptive (meaning primarily selected for in and of itself)
  • that language as a by-product exists as a natural result of human complexity
  • and that language evolved first for inner thought, and was only later co-opted in order to communicate with others

Criticisms for the BPH

When it comes to anything pre-history related, it might be better for us all to just go ahead and accept that nothing will truly ever be as straightforward as we might like it. Naturally, then, it will come as no surprise to you that there are a few key problems with the By-Product Hypothesis.

2.2 The Adaptationist Hypothesis

Although both the By-Product Hypothesis and The Adaptationist Hypothesis implicate natural selection in the evolution of the faulty of language, the latter maintains that in order for this notion to have any validity, language must, then, result as a direct consequence of adaptive selection for purposes of communication (13).

  • that language is adaptative, not exaptive, and therefore comes as a result of primary natural selection

The talking takeaway

Interestingly, some further support for the Adaptationist Hypothesis arises when the maladaptive qualities related to the human capacity for language are considered.

  1. Lieberman, P. (1984). The biology and evolution of language. Harvard University Press.
  2. Christiansen, MH, Chater, N, & Reali, F (2009). The biological and cultural foundations of language. Commun Integr Biol. 2009;2(3):221–222. doi:10.4161/cib.2.3.8034
  3. Fahim, M., & Haghani, M. (2012). Sociocultural Perspectives on Foreign Language Learning. Journal of Language Teaching and Research. Academy Publisher.
  4. Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Socio-cultural theory. Mind in society, 52–58.
  5. Christiansen, MH, Chater, N, & Reali, F (2009). The biological and cultural foundations of language. Commun Integr Biol. 2009;2(3):221–222. doi:10.4161/cib.2.3.8034
  6. de Boysson-Bardies, B., Sagart, L., & Durand, C. (1984). Discernible differences in the babbling of infants according to target language. Journal of child language, 11(1), 1–15.
  7. Chomsky, N. (1998). On the nature, use and acquisition of language. Language and meaning in cognitive science: cognitive issues and semantic theory, 1–20.
  8. Gould, S. J. (1997). The exaptive excellence of spandrels as a term and prototype. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 94(20), 10750–10755.
  9. Gould, S. J. (1997). The exaptive excellence of spandrels as a term and prototype. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 94(20), 10750–10755.
  10. Darwin, C. (1873). The Origin of Species (Murray, London), 6th Ed.
  11. Gould, S. J. (1997). The exaptive excellence of spandrels as a term and prototype. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 94(20), 10750–10755.
  12. Pinker, S., & Bloom, P. (1992). Natural language and natural selection. The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture, 451–493.
  13. Nowak, M. A., Komarova, N. L., & Niyogi, P. (2001). Evolution of universal grammar. Science, 291(5501), 114–118.
  14. Simpson, G. G. (1953). The baldwin effect. Evolution, 7(2), 110–117.
  15. Heimlich, H. J. (1977). The Heimlich maneuver: prevention of death from choking on foreign bodies. Journal of Occupational and Environmental Medicine, 19(3), 208–210